Construction of the Subset S - 7.3 | 7. Cantor's Theorem | Discrete Mathematics - Vol 2
K12 Students

Academics

AI-Powered learning for Grades 8–12, aligned with major Indian and international curricula.

Professionals

Professional Courses

Industry-relevant training in Business, Technology, and Design to help professionals and graduates upskill for real-world careers.

Games

Interactive Games

Fun, engaging games to boost memory, math fluency, typing speed, and English skills—perfect for learners of all ages.

7.3 - Construction of the Subset S

Enroll to start learning

You’ve not yet enrolled in this course. Please enroll for free to listen to audio lessons, classroom podcasts and take practice test.

Practice

Interactive Audio Lesson

Listen to a student-teacher conversation explaining the topic in a relatable way.

Understanding Cardinality

Unlock Audio Lesson

0:00
Teacher
Teacher

Let's start with the concept of cardinality. Cardinality refers to the number of elements in a set. How many of you can tell me the cardinality of the set {1, 2, 3}?

Student 1
Student 1

The cardinality is 3 since there are three elements.

Teacher
Teacher

Exactly! Now, what about a finite set of cardinality 'n'? How does that relate to its power set?

Student 2
Student 2

The power set has 2^n elements, right?

Teacher
Teacher

That's correct! So if we have a set with 'n' elements, the power set will always have more elements. This is foundational for understanding Cantor's theorem.

Student 3
Student 3

So can we always say that n < 2^n?

Teacher
Teacher

Yes, that's a crucial part of our upcoming discussion. Let's remember that: for any finite set, n is less than its power set!

Cantor’s Diagonalization Argument

Unlock Audio Lesson

0:00
Teacher
Teacher

Now, let's shift to infinite sets and delve into Cantor's diagonalization argument. What do you think happens when we try to compare an infinite set with its power set?

Student 4
Student 4

I think it might be different than finite sets, but I’m not sure how.

Teacher
Teacher

Great intuition! Cantor proved that even for infinite sets, their cardinality is less than that of their power sets. Here's how it works: assume there is a surjective function from A to P(A).

Student 1
Student 1

What’s a surjective function again?

Teacher
Teacher

A surjective function is one where every element in the codomain is mapped by at least one element in the domain. So we assume such a function exists. But we will show it leads to a contradiction!

Student 2
Student 2

How do we do that?

Teacher
Teacher

By constructing a set S based on the outputs of this function. Let's explore that!

Constructing the Subset S

Unlock Audio Lesson

0:00
Teacher
Teacher

Now we need to construct the subset S using the diagonalization argument. Are you all ready?

Student 3
Student 3

Yes! But how exactly do we create S?

Teacher
Teacher

We take the diagonal of the function's output and flip each entry. For instance, if f(x_1) has 0, we include x_1 in S, and if it has 1, we exclude it. Can anyone give me an example?

Student 4
Student 4

If f(x_1) has 0, and we change it to 1, would that mean x_1 is included in S?

Teacher
Teacher

Exactly! And we continue this for each element ii. By doing this, we create a set S that cannot map back to any of the images defined by the surjective function f. So what does that mean?

Student 1
Student 1

It means f can't be surjective!

Teacher
Teacher

Precisely! Thus we arrive at a contradiction, and consequently, the assumption of a surjective function must be false.

Introduction & Overview

Read a summary of the section's main ideas. Choose from Basic, Medium, or Detailed.

Quick Overview

Cantor's theorem demonstrates that the cardinality of any set is strictly less than the cardinality of its power set, using a diagonalization argument.

Standard

In this section, we explore Cantor's theorem, which reveals that any set's cardinality is less than that of its power set. The proof involves a diagonalization argument, illustrating that no surjective function can map a set to its power set, thereby proving that there are infinitely many sizes of infinity.

Detailed

Detailed Summary

In this section, we delve into Cantor's theorem, which posits that the cardinality of any set A is strictly less than the cardinality of its power set P(A), the set of all subsets of A.

  1. Finite Sets: For a finite set A with n elements, its power set contains 2^n elements, and it can be easily shown that n < 2^n.
  2. Infinite Sets: Cantor extended this result to infinite sets, proving that even for infinite sets, the cardinality of A is less than that of its power set
    P(A). The proof employs a contradiction approach using a diagonalization argument:
  3. Assume there is a surjective function f from the set A to its power set P(A).
  4. Construct a subset S of A that contains elements based on the diagonal entries of the function's output. Specifically, the inclusion or exclusion of elements in S is determined by flipping the diagonal values.
  5. Demonstrate that this subset S cannot be the image of any element in A, thereby contradicting the existence of the surjective function f.
  6. Implications: As a consequence, Cantor’s theorem implies that the set of natural numbers has a cardinality that is strictly less than that of its power set, indicating that the power set of the natural numbers is uncountable. This leads to the compelling conclusion that there are indeed infinite sizes of infinity, creating a hierarchy of infinite sets.

Youtube Videos

One Shot of Discrete Mathematics for Semester exam
One Shot of Discrete Mathematics for Semester exam

Audio Book

Dive deep into the subject with an immersive audiobook experience.

Cantor's Theorem Overview

Unlock Audio Book

Signup and Enroll to the course for listening the Audio Book

Cantor proved that for any set A, the cardinality (size) of that set is strictly less than the cardinality of its power set P(A), which is the set of all subsets of A.

Detailed Explanation

Cantor's theorem tells us that no matter how many elements a set A has, when you create a power set of A (P(A)), which includes all possible subsets of A, that power set will always have more elements than A itself. For example, if you have a finite set with n elements, the power set will have 2^n elements. This relationship holds true even for infinite sets, which is a surprising result.

Examples & Analogies

Think of a box of chocolates as set A. You can take out different combinations of chocolates to create subsets. The total number of ways to select chocolates (the power set, P(A)) is far greater than the number of chocolates in the box itself. Even if you have just a few chocolates, you can create many possible combinations.

Assuming a Surjective Function

Unlock Audio Book

Signup and Enroll to the course for listening the Audio Book

Assuming the cardinality of set A is greater than or equal to its power set P(A), we denote a surjective function from A to P(A) as f.

Detailed Explanation

To explore the implications of Cantor's theorem, we start by assuming that the size of set A is at least as large as the size of its power set. This assumption leads us to define a function f that supposedly creates a mapping from each element in A to a subset in P(A). However, this assumption forms the basis for a contradiction, as we will show that this function cannot exist.

Examples & Analogies

Imagine you have a box of crayons (set A), and you are trying to create a system to map each crayon to a specific drawing you can make with it (P(A)). You think you can assign each crayon to a unique drawing. However, as we’ll discover, no matter how many crayons you have, some drawings will always remain unassigned.

Constructing the Subset S

Unlock Audio Book

Signup and Enroll to the course for listening the Audio Book

We run a diagonalization argument to construct a subset S of A that is not covered by the function f.

Detailed Explanation

Using the diagonalization approach, we can create a new subset S by examining the diagonal entries of the supposed function f. For each entry along the diagonal, we flip 0s to 1s and 1s to 0s, which means that the constructed subset S will differ from every subset f(x) that was supposed to be covered by f. Hence, S cannot be the image of any element in A under f, proving that our initial assumption about f being a surjective function is false.

Examples & Analogies

Consider a library where every book represents a different subset of a collection (P(A)). Think of the main characters of each book as the diagonal entries. By changing the character features (flipping 0s and 1s), you create a new book that doesn't match any existing one. Just like the new book is different from all others, the constructed subset S is not assigned to any crayon originally mapped, thereby proving our contradiction.

Conclusion of the Proof

Unlock Audio Book

Signup and Enroll to the course for listening the Audio Book

Since the constructed subset S does not have any pre-image, the assumption of a surjective function being valid is contradicted.

Detailed Explanation

The existence of the subset S, which cannot be represented as f(x) for any x in A, shows a fundamental flaw in our assumption that there is a surjective function from A to P(A). Therefore, it confirms that the cardinality of A is indeed less than that of its power set, validating Cantor's theorem.

Examples & Analogies

Returning to our library analogy, every book represented by function f has certain characters. When we create a new book (S), we find that it cannot be categorized under any existing mapping. This reinforces our understanding that our library of books (A) is always smaller than the infinite possibilities (P(A)) of the stories that could be told with those characters.

Implications of Cantor's Theorem

Unlock Audio Book

Signup and Enroll to the course for listening the Audio Book

Cantor’s theorem implies that there are infinite sizes of infinity—showing that the power set of any infinite set is uncountable.

Detailed Explanation

Cantor's theorem reveals that there are different 'sizes' or cardinalities of infinity. For example, the set of natural numbers is countable and has a cardinality denoted as א₀. However, its power set is uncountable, meaning there are more subsets than natural numbers. This concept leads to a hierarchy of infinities, where you can continue constructing power sets indefinitely, each leading to a larger cardinality.

Examples & Analogies

Consider a bug (natural numbers) that always hops to higher ground (power set). Each time it hops, it finds more ground (larger power sets) than it can ever reach in its previous state, illustrating how infinities can be of different 'sizes' and how there is no end to how large they can grow.

Definitions & Key Concepts

Learn essential terms and foundational ideas that form the basis of the topic.

Key Concepts

  • Cantor's Theorem: States that the cardinality of any set is strictly less than the cardinality of its power set.

  • Diagonalization: A method for proving that no surjective function exists from a set to its power set.

  • Surjective Function: A function where each element in the codomain has a pre-image in the domain.

  • Infinite Sets: Sets that have unbounded cardinality, such as the set of natural numbers.

  • Hierarchy of Infinities: The idea that there are different sizes of infinite sets.

Examples & Real-Life Applications

See how the concepts apply in real-world scenarios to understand their practical implications.

Examples

  • The set {1, 2, 3} has a cardinality of 3, and its power set contains {∅, {1}, {2}, {3}, {1,2}, {1,3}, {2,3}, {1,2,3}} which has 2^3 = 8 elements.

  • For the infinite set of natural numbers, Cantor's theorem shows that the cardinality of the power set is greater than that of the natural numbers, illustrating multiple infinities.

Memory Aids

Use mnemonics, acronyms, or visual cues to help remember key information more easily.

🎵 Rhymes Time

  • A power set's size is two to the n, it grows so wide, it's quite the zen!

📖 Fascinating Stories

  • Imagine a classroom with students (elements). If every student represents a subset, the power set becomes all the combinations, small and grand!

🧠 Other Memory Gems

  • To remember that cardinality of a set is less than its power set, use: 'Less is always more, think power score!'

🎯 Super Acronyms

CSP (Cantor's Surjectivity Proof) - shows that no surjective mapping can exist from any set to its power set.

Flash Cards

Review key concepts with flashcards.

Glossary of Terms

Review the Definitions for terms.

  • Term: Cardinality

    Definition:

    The number of elements in a set, indicating its size.

  • Term: Power Set

    Definition:

    The set of all subsets of a set.

  • Term: Surjective Function

    Definition:

    A function where every element in the codomain has at least one corresponding element in the domain.

  • Term: Diagonalization Argument

    Definition:

    A method used to construct a new element that differs from each given element in a systematic way.

  • Term: Contradiction

    Definition:

    A logical conflict that arises when an assumption leads to an impossible situation.